Hidden in Plain View: Feminists Doing Engineering Ethics, Engineers Doing Feminist Ethics

Hidden in Plain View: Feminists Doing Engineering Ethics, Engineers Doing Feminist Ethics
After watch the video and read the article, you have to answer this question:
-What do you think about Riley’s ideas on epistemology? In general, epistemology is the study of knowledge, but here we mean it in the context of the creation and
dissemination of knowledge in a particular area of inquiry: culturally induced values and beliefs. She argues that part of the reason that engineering ethics lacks a
concern or an inclusion of feminist ideas is because of this epistemological issue and how the powers that be, the existing infrastructure and culture control the
dialogue by controlling how we can talk about certain issues. Do you agree with her?
Hidden in Plain View: Feminists Doing Engineering
Ethics, Engineers Doing Feminist Ethics
Donna Riley
Received: 26 May 2011 / Accepted: 14 October 2011 / Published online: 28 October 2011
Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2011
Abstract How has engineering ethics addressed gender concerns to date? How
have the ideas of feminist philosophers and feminist ethicists made their way into
engineering ethics? What might an explicitly feminist engineering ethics look like?
This paper reviews some major themes in feminist ethics and then considers three
areas in which these themes have been taken up in engineering ethics to date. First,
Caroline Whitbeck’s work in engineering ethics integrates considerations from her
own earlier writings and those of other feminist philosophers, but does not use the
feminist label. Second, efforts to incorporate the Ethic of Care and principles of
Social Justice into engineering have drawn on feminist scholarship and principles,
but these commitments can be lost in translation to the broader engineering community.
Third, the film Henry’s Daughters brings gender considerations into the
mainstream of engineering ethics, but does not draw on feminist ethics per se;
despite the best intentions in broaching a difficult subject, the film unfortunately
does more harm than good when it comes to sexual harassment education. I seek not
only to make the case that engineers should pay attention to feminist ethics and
engineering ethicists make more use of feminist ethics traditions in the field, but
also to provide some avenues for how to approach integrating feminist ethics in
engineering. The literature review and analysis of the three examples point to future
work for further developing what might be called feminist engineering ethics.
I intend the phrase ‘‘feminist engineering ethics’’ to represent a variety of feminist approaches to
engineering ethics and engineers’ approaches to feminist ethics. Walker (1989) among others has
cautioned us against singular approaches to feminist ethics that re-establish hegemonic systems of
thought. Here I focus on what engineers can learn from feminist ethics rather than the converse. Though
there is likely a case to be made that feminist ethicists may have something to learn from engineers, as an
engineer I hesitate to speculate in any detail about these synergies until a conversation between feminist
ethicists and engineers has progressed further.
D. Riley (&)
Picker Engineering Program, Smith College, 155 Ford Hall, Northampton, MA 01063, USA
e-mail: driley@smith.edu
123
Sci Eng Ethics (2013) 19:189–206
DOI 10.1007/s11948-011-9320-0
Keywords Care Justice Agency Sexual harassment Feminist engineering
ethics
Introduction
Feminist legal ethics, feminist business ethics, and feminist medical ethics are well
established fields of scholarship (Holmes and Purdy 1992; Larson and Freeman
1997; Mashburn and Martin 19991
). Yet the phrase ‘‘feminist engineering ethics’’ is
rarely if ever uttered; at the time of this writing googling the exact phrase ‘‘feminist
engineering ethics’’ produces no results whatsoever. What might be the benefits of
bringing the work of feminist ethics to bear on scholarship in engineering ethics?
What might engineering ethicists offer the field of feminist ethics? Interestingly, one
can find the ideas of feminist philosophers and feminist ethicists in some
engineering ethics scholarship, but the feminist label has been conspicuously
dropped. What might account for both the late appearance of feminist ethics in
engineering, and the decision of some scholars to closet their works’ feminist
orientation?
To begin to answer these questions, in this article I review key ideas from
feminist ethics that speak to engineering education and practice. I then explore how
engineering ethics has addressed gender concerns to date by examining three
separate and significant contexts in which feminist scholarship has emerged in
engineering ethics. First, the work of feminist philosopher and engineering ethicist
Caroline Whitbeck blends feminist thought into engineering ethics, but without
naming it as such. Second, groups of scholars have sought to bring notions of care,
and separately notions of justice, into engineering ethics curricula, echoing
conversations from a large body of scholarship in feminist ethics. Third, the most
recent video from the National Institute for Engineering Ethics, Henry’s Daughters,
explicitly takes up gender concerns, particularly sexual harassment, as an ethical
issue. In this case the film largely fails to connect with feminist scholarship. In
critically examining all three of these efforts to combine engineering ethics with
feminist or gender concerns, I hope to constructively point to areas where more
work is needed. In closing, I propose some ways forward for developing explicitly
feminist approaches to engineering ethics.
This effort grows out of a workshop I attended on feminist ethics at DePauw
University in June 2010. An engineer by training, I first approached the field of
engineering ethics in a graduate course, then as a participant in a Graduate Research
Ethics Education (GREE) workshop, and as an instructor of ethics for undergraduate
researchers. Later as an engineering faculty member, I incorporated ethics into my
courses and into our overall curriculum through collaboration with other faculty
(Riley et al. 2004, 2006). My approach to scholarship on gender emerged first from
an activist’s perspective in college, and ultimately led to a departmental affiliation
1 While Mashburn and Martin argue that the field of feminist legal ethics is underdeveloped, the fact that
they use the phrase ‘‘feminist legal ethics’’ in a book chapter reviewing that field demonstrates far greater
development than in engineering.
190 D. Riley
123
with gender studies at my institution. I began exploring feminist ethics while
preparing a course on science, technology and ethics that incorporates both feminist
ethics and feminist and postcolonial science and technology studies (Riley 2008).
The DePauw workshop provided me with a solid introductory background to the
feminist ethics literature, and helped me to think about major themes in feminist
ethics that are most relevant to engineering and engineering ethics.
Feminist Ethics: Some Major Themes
It is not possible to provide a comprehensive summary of feminist ethics here, but it
is important to introduce scholars in the engineering ethics community to some of
the most relevant themes in feminist ethics that may intersect productively with
engineering ethics. This review focuses on key insights from feminist scholarship in
five thematic areas: critiques of masculinist (androcentric) ethics; questions of
power and moral agency; the debate over justice and care; feminist professional
ethics; and applied feminist ethics specifically related to science and technology.
Critiques of Masculinist Ethics
Feminist scholarship often begins from a place of critique, examining a body of
knowledge or existing practice that has not been feminist, uncovering sexist norms
(also racist, classist, ageist, ableist, heterosexist, and other norms), identifying ways
in which women and others have been excluded or silenced, and conceiving new
ways forward. Feminist ethicists began in this vein with critiques of masculinist
ethics; they pointed out problems with traditional ethics’ calls to universals,
depersonalization, and abstraction, in which relationships and social or political
context are mere distractions (Walker 1989). Feminist ethicists argued that this onesize-fits
all, decontextualized approach was systematically excluding certain values
and moral considerations. What Walker calls an ‘‘alternative epistemology’’
emerged that introduced feminist ways of knowing in ethics. These approaches
require attention to specific persons, as opposed to abstract ideals, emphasizing
relationality. A focus on relationships in turn necessitates the construction of
narratives, which provide context for ethical consideration. For narratives to be
appropriately understood and taken into account requires the ability to communicate.
Just as ‘‘the personal is political’’ for feminists, the personal is also moral, and
the moral is personal.
Walker (1989) further notes that attention to context also means the moral is
political; the construction of cases and their analysis embodies a politics of language
and a politics of academic and social institutions. Thus feminist ethicists examine
rhetoric and discourse around an issue or situation, ask who is a moral agent, and
how social structures constrain or facilitate agency. Resisting universals, depersonalization
and abstraction means that feminists must wrestle with ‘‘moral
remainders’’—the unfinished business that is left to us when ethical decisions are
necessarily imperfect and we must attend to the relational fallout.
Hidden in Plain View 191
123
To illustrate how these concerns play out in working through ethical problems, it
may be helpful to consider an example from the field of bioethics. Parks (1999)
explicates how ethical androcentrism manifests itself in the particular case of
maternal substance addiction, and how a feminist approach leads to very different
treatment decisions.
Ethical androcentrism presumes a self that is atomistic, independent, selfsufficient,
rational, and willing; the moral agent, on this view, does his moral
reasoning in an ideal state, where his reason is ‘‘pure’’ (that is, untainted by
contingencies), he is free from the influence of others, and he can take an
objectivist ‘‘view from nowhere’’ (167).
These androcentric ethics exist in a medical field that also retains a male bias;
Parks notes that despite the fact that 40% of substance addicts are women, they
comprise only 7% of research subjects in this field. With addiction defined as a male
problem, treatment programs also take this atomistic approach in which individuals
come to control their addictions in isolation from social factors like poverty, racism,
or mental health issues that might affect one’s addiction. Few addiction treatment
programs address the needs of pregnant women or women with children, rendering
their addiction invisible, and giving addicted women few places to turn. At the same
time, pregnant addicts are often targeted out of concern for their fetuses in ways that
stigmatize or punish the woman. An androcentric conception of moral agents as
rational decision makers uninfluenced by social forces causes pregnant women who
are addicted to be labeled ‘‘prenatal abusers,’’ ascribing intent to life circumstances
often beyond the woman’s control. Parks argues that a feminist approach would
consider the systems of power in which addiction occurs, including poverty, racism,
and lack of access to health care. Responses such as institutionalization, incarceration,
and forced sterilization are no longer ethically defensible; instead, research on
female addicts and their particular challenges and needs can lead to appropriate
treatment and prevention of addiction, affording moral standing to women, not just
the fetuses within them.
Power and Moral Agency
At the heart of feminist approaches is a concern about power. Feminist ethicists
understand moral agency in terms of power, asking who is recognized as a moral
agent, and how agency is constrained or facilitated by power relations. Andrew
(2001) notes that feminist ethics has the potential to establish women as empowered
moral agents. Nelson (2001) argues that identity (e.g., as female, as queer, as Latina)
is linked to moral agency. How others identify a person can constrain that person’s
range of moral agency, and how people identify themselves can influence their own
awareness of their ability to act. Interestingly, Nelson uses a professional ethics case
to illustrate her point, in which a doctor makes the call not to tell a patient he has
leukemia; a nurse questions this decision. When the doctor dismisses the nurse’s
professional moral judgment as emotional over-involvement, the nurse works with
her peers to develop a counter-story that reclaims the nurses’ moral agency as
professionals.
192 D. Riley
123
While some early conceptions of feminism understood power in terms of gender
alone, women of color writing in the area of feminist theory developed the idea of
intersectionality, critiquing gender as the sole category of analysis and characterizing
how multiple identities (race, gender, class, sexuality, ability, and other identities)
operate simultaneously to shape one’s experience of oppression and privilege (hooks
1984; Crenshaw 1991). Building on this work, transnational feminism works at the
intersection of nationhood and economic condition (in addition to race, gender, and
sexuality) to resist globalization and imperialism (Harding and Narayan 1998;
Narayan and Harding 1998; Jaggar 2009a). For example, Kittay (2009) analyzes the
practices of migrant carework, articulating the kinds of moral harm done when caring
labor is commodified in a global economic framework, and workers sacrifice the
most significant relationships in their own lives to care for others’ families.
Justice, Care, and Beyond
In the 1970s and 1980s, as feminists sought to bring women into an ethical picture
that had previously excluded them as moral agents, some significant early work
focused on difference, and on what had been left out of moral theorizing done
mostly by men. This work often utilized experiences that were either stereotypically
or ‘‘biologically’’ women’s domain—caring, nurturance, and motherhood—seeking
to bring focus to relationality absent in traditional ethics. Noddings (1984) critiqued
conceptions of rights and justice that had ignored relationships, offering as an
alternative an ‘‘Ethic of Care’’, building on Gilligan’s (1982) observation of
difference in how men and women spoke about ethical questions: men tended to use
rights language, and women the language of relationships and care for others.
Care Ethics was later criticized as potentially re-inscribing women’s subordination
(Bartky 1995). Card (1995), for example, posits that women’s tendency to care
is constructed from power dynamics that restrict women’s choices. She cautions
against an ethic emphasizing relationship when not all relationships are healthy.
Narayan (1995) builds on the notion of unjust power relations in Care Ethics by
chronicling the role of ‘‘care’’ in the history of colonialism, where patronizing
imperial interests justified their actions as caring for those less fortunate, denying
others’ agency. While some care ethicists (Tronto 1987, 1993; Warren 2000) bring
considerations of power into the Ethic of Care, questions remain about how to
address injustice or how to engage the uncaring or the uncared-for in society.
Some feminists have worked within the justice tradition, while critiquing its
flaws. Okin (1989) sought to apply theories of justice to the family as a site of
gender inequality. Young (1990) challenged narrow conceptions of justice as
distributive, offering instead a framework based on oppression and domination. She
shows how denial of difference facilitates oppression, while challenging oppression
in its multiple forms can allow for true participation from a diverse public. Cannon
(1988) draws on the experience of black women in history and literature to locate
justice as a central theme in black womanist ethics. More recently Vidhu (2004) has
called for a critique of development in terms of feminist theories of justice and
Jaggar (2009b) has used Iris Young’s concept of gendered vulnerability to add a
gender dimension to theories of global justice.
Hidden in Plain View 193
123
Some have argued that justice and care frames are complementary or compatible
(Koehn 1998; Held 1995); both provide a departure from traditional, masculinist
ethics, though neither is without its flaws. Thus, we are left in a place of living with
the inadequacy of imperfect theories; a universal theory may be not only elusive, but
also undesirable (Walker 1989).
Feminist Ethics and Professional Ethics
Business, law and medicine—professions engineers often choose as sites of
comparison—have traditions in professional ethics explicitly labeled feminist. Other
professions such as social work also have longstanding feminist ethics traditions
that are an integral part of their mainstream professional ethics (Hugman and Smith
1995).
Feminist legal ethics has entertained the care-justice debate as a central focus,
with some scholars also writing on contextual analysis, postmodern and ethnographic
approaches to narratives, and the inclusion of multiple voices (Taylor et al.
1999). Feminist business ethics has addressed communication and the importance of
listening (Derry 2002) and has taken up the question of who is a moral agent, using
care ethics to revise stakeholder analysis (Wicks et al. 1994; Burton and Dunn
1996). Feminists have critiqued the epistemological and ideological assumptions of
traditional business ethics and made visible its construction in a sexist, racist, and
classist setting and its support of patriarchal and capitalist power structures (Larson
and Freeman 1997). Walker’s (1989) characterization of the space of feminist ethics
appears to represent well the kinds of issues that have emerged within these
particular professions, and that we might expect to see in feminist engineering
ethics.
Writing about professional ethics as a whole, Tronto (2001) considers recent
trends toward the management of professions that were once considered autonomous.
On the one hand, she finds autonomy of professions problematic because it
excludes non-professionals’ participation in ethical decisions. However, she also
finds it problematic to place managers in a position of power over professionals
making ethics decisions. A manager, whose expertise is in organizational management,
may seek to constrain actions that seem to go above and beyond what is
expected within the organizational structure. However, professionals acquainted
with particular norms of practice may see such actions as being ethically required.
Tronto challenges professionals to recognize the collective nature of competence and
make professional boundaries more porous, to see how power, distance and hierarchy
can undermine professional competence rather than maintain it.
Applications
One way to move beyond the care-justice debate is to ground oneself in the context
of real lives and real problems. Such work is inherently interdisciplinary,
encompassing women and gender studies, political science, sociology, history,
and other disciplines. While philosophers may not always recognize interdisciplinary
scholarship as ‘‘ethics’’, these sites of inquiry hold great promise for feminist
194 D. Riley
123
ethics because they ground ethical problems in women’s lives through multiple
lenses, epistemologies and methodologies. Many applications of feminist ethics
intersect with engineering: reproduction and bioethics; ecology and environment;
transnational feminism, globalization, and development; and war and militarism
(Riley 2008). Many of these topics are also taken up by feminist science and
technology studies scholars (e.g., Cockburn and Dubravk 2002; Cowan 1992;
Subramaniam 2001; Wacjman 1991). Unfortunately these discussions rarely cross
engineering’s disciplinary boundaries. Work in feminist ethics ought to be
recognized as part of the field of engineering ethics, but feminist approaches and
topics are not typically included. The problems here are closely related to the
challenges identified by those working at the intersection of science and technology
studies (STS) and engineering ethics (Johnson and Wetmore 2008), where certain
types or scales of analysis are not adopted as part of engineering ethics, and STS
eschews work that is too applied to engineering ethics as interventionist.
Caroline Whitbeck: Feminist Ethics by Any Other Name
Caroline Whitbeck is an engineering ethicist who was also a groundbreaking
feminist philosopher in the 1970s and 1980s. Early on she learned first-hand about
power/knowledge relations in the academy. In writing about maternity in the early
1970s, Whitbeck found that accepted philosophical forms of expression emphasized
intellect to the exclusion of embodiment, presenting a major obstacle to writing
from her experience of motherhood. She reflected on this in her Afterword to ‘The
Maternal Instinct’: ‘‘Lesson: if you are introducing new content, it is more readily
received if you work within accepted forms—the problem is that the forms
themselves make it impossible to deal adequately with certain content…’’
(Whitbeck 1983: 195). Whitbeck’s engineering ethics complies with conventional
forms, but it also builds on a foundation in feminist philosophy. What might be left
out from her work (and others’) because of the forms demanded in engineering
ethics? To bring to the fore what is feminist in Whitbeck’s work, in this section I
contrast her approach with what I consider to be typical or mainstream approaches
to engineering ethics, exemplified by three well-known, best-selling and enduring
textbooks in engineering ethics (Fleddermann 1999; Harris et al. 2005; Martin and
Schinzinger 1996).
One of the main contributions to engineering ethics credited to Whitbeck is the
‘‘agent-centered’’ approach to teaching engineering ethics, in which students are
placed in the role of ethical actor (Whitbeck 1995). This builds on a shift away from
theoretical abstractions toward a case-based approach, but instead of students
playing the role of ‘‘judge’’ reviewing cases—another form of abstraction—they are
placed in the role of decision-maker. While this attention to agency can be
supported by any number of arguments, including learner-centered approaches to
engineering education, it resonates strongly with previous work of feminist
philosophers on power and moral agency.
Hidden in Plain View 195
123
Whitbeck (1995) notes that while problems in ethics are often presented as a
conflict between two alternatives, it is more appropriate to think of them as subject
to multiple constraints (like engineering design problems), not all of which may
necessarily be met. This seems to echo Walker’s (1989) discussion of ‘‘moral
remainders.’’ However, while moral remainders are static—an imperfect solution
we must settle for—design within constraints leaves open the possibility of
continual iteration toward a creative solution that, while not necessarily perfect,
may be a little better each time.
In Whitbeck’s (1998) textbook, she fully develops the analogy between ethics
and design in a section entitled ‘‘ethics as design: doing justice to ethical problems.’’
This seems problematic at first: will the engineering design process be uncritically
plunked down on top of ethics problems? Will the author take a reductionist
approach to moral problem-solving complete with flow diagrams as in traditional
texts (Harris et al. 2005; Fleddermann 1999)? Can the promise of ‘‘doing justice,’’
itself unusual in the world of engineering ethics, be fulfilled? This section of the text
does not rush in with an ill-fitting model, as engineers are often wont to do. Rather it
focuses on drawing moral lessons from the design process for approaching ethical
problems. There is no directive of steps to follow; instead important concepts are
identified and interpreted, such as how to deal with ambiguity. If one compares
texts, Whitbeck’s work stands as a critique of the moral problem-solving approach
presented in Harris et al. (2005) and Fleddermann (1999).
The third element, scattered throughout Whitbeck’s book, is mentions of feminist
philosophers, prominent women, and feminist cases as a matter of course. These are
rarely or never mentioned in other engineering ethics texts, and include environmental
advocates Rachel Carson and Lois Gibbs, female whistleblower Inez Austin,
and feminist thinkers Annette Baier, Iris Young, Carol Gilligan, Kathryn Addelson,
Martha Nussbaum, and Natalie Dandekar. Cases include the Montreal Massacre
(misogynist and explicitly anti-feminist mass murder of women engineers at the
University of Montreal), Harris v. Forklift (sexual harassment case), and the Dalkon
shield intrauterine device. These acts of inclusion point out what we’ve been
missing and implicitly call out masculinist bias in other mainstream texts.
Whitbeck’s book also stands out in its explicit mention of racism (the use of the
actual word, rare in engineering—p. 228). Race comes up in discussions of the
Tuskegee Syphilis experiments, the Civil Rights Act of 1964, and environmental
justice. Whitbeck raises class issues in her discussion of professional autonomy,
echoing some but not all of Tronto’s (2001) concerns about professional ethics and
power relations of professionals with respect to the public and to management.
Broaching these subjects in a fashion that is true to feminist concerns breaks
important new ground in engineering ethics and calls attention to the work yet to be
done.
It might be noted that Martin and Schinzinger (1996) also take up the issue of
racism (and reference the Ethic of Care without mentioning feminism). However,
perhaps in order to maintain palatability to an engineering audience, they put on an
appearance of objectivity or balance that undermines any project of dismantling
racism. They consider discrimination and reverse discrimination as if they might be
the same, as if one can erase the historical legacy of slavery in the United States, as
196 D. Riley
123
if one can pretend there are no structural inequalities based on race in the present
day. They approach labor issues similarly, at first taking a critical look at anti-union
clauses in professional codes but failing to offer any analysis of power, ultimately
concluding that ‘‘it is not always obvious that a strike or other collective, forceful
action on the part of employees is unprofessional, excessively self-interested, or
disloyal to employers’’ (205). By conceding racist, sexist, and anti-labor framings of
the problems they consider, they limit the moral space of available action.
Whitbeck locates women’s lives and experiences in the center of her book and
incorporates the ideas of feminist philosophers, but she stops short of entering headon
into foundational debates in ethics. She acknowledges a number of philosophers
who have critiqued abstract reason as the sole basis for ethics (including feminist
ethicists Kathryn Addelson, Annette Baier, and Iris Marion Young as well as
philosophers who argue rationality is contextual and/or socially constructed
including Alasdair MacIntyre, John McDermott, and Bernard Williams). Whitbeck
states that although she takes up some of their work in the book, she does not deal
directly with the content of feminist and other alternative normative ethical theories.
What is lost, and what is gained, from this strategy?
Feminist ethics are hidden in plain view because at no point does Whitbeck label
her approach, or the approach of other feminist philosophers she cites, as feminist.
Interestingly, feminists are mentioned as targets of the Montreal Massacre. This
is particularly poignant because one of the women wounded in the shooting,
engineering student Nathalie Provost, pleaded with the killer to spare her life,
saying, ‘‘No, it’s not true. We’re not feminists’’ (Weston and Aubry 1990). What is
at stake when we use or shun the feminist label in engineering?
Whitbeck’s work makes visible a set of strategic choices one feminist
philosopher has made in connecting feminist ethics and engineering ethics. They
reflect in some sense her perception of what connections would be well received in
engineering ethics, and what would be a bridge too far. Both the literal violence
done to perceived feminists in the Montreal Massacre and the power relations of
what can be produced as knowledge within masculinist fields contributes to an
environment in which ‘‘feminism’’ is maintained as a bad word in engineering as
well as in engineering ethics. In the next section we will consider the work of
multiple scholars in the areas of care and justice that reflect additional strategies
around this ‘‘feminist problem’’ in engineering ethics.
Care and Justice: Adaptations and Co-Optations
Engineering educators have drawn on both care and justice conceptions of feminist
ethics in their work. Rather than an oppositional framing, there is a both-and
approach, or at least a respectful tolerance of both approaches, in engineering,
perhaps because the community of scholars working on either is small and forming,
or perhaps because late adoption has allowed for reliance on scholars who have
resolved or moved beyond justice versus care (Riley et al. 2009). At the same time,
the concepts of care and justice have become distorted in some applications within
engineering ethics. I point these out here in hopes of clarifying some of the
Hidden in Plain View 197
123
meanings of care and justice in feminist ethics scholarship, so that engineering
ethicists can either use these concepts with greater frequency and fidelity, or else
more definitively differentiate their perspectives from those of feminist ethicists.
Advocates of the Ethic of Care in engineering include Pantazidou and Nair
(1999), who like Whitbeck make use of a design analogy. Rather than drawing
lessons from design for approaching problems in ethics, in this case they proceed in
the opposite direction, and ask what lessons can be drawn from the Ethic of Care for
the design process in engineering. They re-think the design process in terms of care,
using Tronto’s (1987, 1993) conceptions that take power into account. Similar to
Whitbeck, they do not identify Tronto or the Ethic of Care as feminist.
This work opens the door for future re-imagining of other forms of engineering
thought. The analogy to design begs the question of how care might be brought to
bear on engineering problem solving. Asking this question would require a critique
of the traditional engineering problem-solving approach, its abstractions, its
reductionism, and its ignorance of relationships, narrative, and context. In short,
it would be a feminist critique of masculinist problem solving in engineering.
Other engineers have adopted and applied the Ethic of Care in specific contexts.
In an extensive treatment, Kardon (2005) seeks to extend the Ethic of Care to a
number of structural engineering ethics cases. However, in Kardon’s work, despite
citations to Tronto, the Ethic of Care dissolves into the ‘‘standard of care’’ of
traditional engineering ethics. The cases are depersonalized, and care is conceptualized
in relation to things—engineering knowledge, calculations, bolt connections.
People factor in a few cases but never directly—an engineer didn’t realize the
significance of a peer’s findings, for example, but nothing is said of respect for or
communication with this individual. Something was lost in translation, and we see
how the phrase ‘‘Ethic of Care’’ can be co-opted (albeit unintentionally) to mean
something quite different than it does in feminist ethics.
Perhaps the strongest critics of care approaches in engineering ethics are Vesilind
and Gunn (1998). While they freely use the label ‘‘feminist’’ in their engineering
ethics textbook, they critique the essentialism of ‘‘some’’ feminist ethicists who link
women with nurturing, cooperation and care (citing only 1970s work from feminist
theologian Mary Daly). However, rather than cite feminists who have offered
critiques of Care, they offer their own argument which appears to misread the
positions of most Care ethicists: ‘‘if men are indeed incapable of developing or
following a feminist ethic, then there could be no such thing as engineering ethics
because there are both male and female engineers’’ (73). Many Care ethicists have
gone out of their way to prevent such a reading, locating care with men as well as
women (e.g., Noddings 1984; Tronto 1987). While I do not necessarily wish to
defend Mary Daly’s argument, I will point out that their defensive reaction—offense
at the specter of men being deprived of moral agency—abstracts Daly’s argument
from its context and shifts the focus away from the real harm done by centuries of
women’s actual deprivation of moral agency. Or, to put it another way, they read a
call to end men’s monopoly on moral agency incorrectly as a claim that men should
have no moral agency at all. Vesilind and Gunn (1998) go on to hold up some
elements of feminist ethics and ecofeminism in the book. Does their critique (or the
198 D. Riley
123
male privilege evidenced therein) create a certain distance from feminist ethics that
enables them to use the label?
Another (sometimes overlapping) group of scholars has sought to discuss justice
approaches (and peace approaches) to engineering (Baillie 2006–2011; Engineering,
Social Justice and Peace 2010; Vesilind 2010). While the justice tradition has been
impacted by feminist scholarship as discussed above, it remains the case that not all
justice approaches are feminist. Within the Engineering, Social Justice and Peace
network, gender justice is an integral part of the conversation, but not everyone
comes to the work out of feminist commitments. Dangers of co-optation exist here
as well, as social justice can be equated with corporate social responsibility and lose
(among other things) its critique of economic systems of oppression.
This is particularly problematic in discussions of poverty and global development.
For example, Kickstart, an engineering non-governmental development
organization, claimed it had ‘‘the tools to end poverty,’’ designed its ‘‘moneymaker
pump’’ to be manufactured and sold locally in several African nations, creating local
jobs for manufacturers and materials producers. However, this strategy was
abandoned as capitalist logic favored cheaper and larger scale production of pumps
in China (McGregor 2006). Karnani (2007) challenges the ‘‘bottom of the pyramid’’
approach of marketing products to the poor in order to end poverty, demonstrating
how it actually exploits the poor, funneling their limited resources to further swell
corporate coffers, delivering products that sell a false sense of empowerment and
even capitalize on racist stereotypes as in the case of skin lightening cream. Allgood
(2010) of Procter and Gamble spoke at the Association of Practical and Professional
Ethics mini-conference on engineering and social justice about that corporation’s
efforts to distribute water filters in a number of developing countries. When pressed
on P&G’s motivations during the question and answer session, Allgood revealed
that while his personal commitment was to deliver clean water to people who
needed it, the bottom line consideration for P&G was gaining brand recognition and
trust among locals in order to market Always menstrual products to women. It is
only through this kind of open, critical discussion of global economic contexts that
we can fully implement social justice analysis in engineering ethics.
The tendency for both justice and care to be co-opted is not specific to
engineering, but it does suggest that any work toward feminist engineering ethics
may need to focus more explicitly on feminism and a clear articulation of values,
and more politically on structures of power in forms of expression, in ways of
knowing, and in professional and academic institutions.
Henry’s Daughters
The film project Henry’s Daughters (2010) is the third effort from the National
Institute for Engineering Ethics (NIEE) at Texas Tech in collaboration with the
Great Projects Film Company (Paul Martin, writer, director, and editor). The films
and accompanying study guides are designed as classroom resources for engineering
educators, and pack many different types of ethics issues into productions lasting
approximately half an hour.
Hidden in Plain View 199
123
Henry’s Daughters sought to close several gaps in topics covered by educational
videos in engineering ethics including a focus on information technology and a
focus on gender and diversity (Loui et al. 2010). Female characters in previous
NIEE films had been part of management or were members of other professions
such as journalism or law. While placing female engineers as central decisionmakers
in the film demonstrates the best intentions of the project team to address
gender as a significant issue in engineering ethics, there are some points of
disconnection with feminist ethics that create a film that is more harmful than
helpful. I personally know members of the project team who are very much
committed to positively addressing gender and diversity issues. I hope that in
developing an understanding of how this film fails from a feminist perspective we
can open new opportunities to forge better connections between feminist ethics and
engineering ethics in the future.
The story focuses on two sisters, Laura and Julie, who face a number of ethical
decisions as engineers throughout the film. To ascribe moral agency to women in an
engineering role is an essential first step in setting up a potentially feminist
framework for encountering ethical issues. The film, however, is not titled ‘‘Laura
and Julie;’’ the women are instead identified by their father (Henry), a prominent
engineer and lobbyist. Titling the film Henry’s Daughters may do some political
work within engineering, reaching older male engineering professors who might
identify more closely with Henry. It also evokes the old trope that men should
respect a woman because she’s somebody’s daughter; respect is mediated through
male protection and ownership. Other characters in the film seem to be aware of this
relationship, as Laura is rumored to have advanced in her job due to Henry’s
connections rather than her own merit. However, this mythology is quietly
dismantled through Laura’s competent actions throughout the film, another element
in the film that can be read as feminist.
The filmmakers’ biggest misstep may have been the decision to take on sexual
harassment as its first foray into gender issues, particularly without significant
expertise in this area guiding the project. The film was distributed widely among
engineering educators for use in the fall semester of 2010, with an invitation to use
the film in courses with students. However, there is no information in the study
guide or cover letter that accompanied the distribution that would help a screener to
be sensitive to audience members who may have experienced sexual harassment and
may come to them for help (or who may find the film upsetting to watch). It does not
suggest engineering educators become informed about their own institution’s
policies and procedures around sexual harassment.2
The film strongly departs from feminist ethics when it reinforces the myth that
sexual harassment is about sexuality and attractiveness rather than about power and
sex discrimination (MacKinnon 1979). Laura, the older daughter, escapes sexual
harassment, while her sister Julie experiences three separate incidents of unwanted
attention in a 32 min film. The film’s explanation for this is that Laura is
2 This is missing despite specific suggestions I and others made at an early screening of the film at the
Association of Practical and Professional Ethics meeting in March 2010.
200 D. Riley
123
unattractive: 32 years old,3 unmarried, living with her sister, a ‘‘dowdy’’ dresser
with no trace of a social life.
This feminist fully supports the idea of presenting alternatives to marriage,
heternormativity, and nuclear families. But to present a viable alternative and
counter stigmas around unmarried women, Laura’s life would need to be full with
balanced interests and healthy relationships. Instead, all we see is work, living with
her sister, and drowning her emotions in cake. For college-age engineering students,
it is not helpful to reinforce the perception (real in its consequences) that female
engineers are not suitable partners (Seymour 1995; Tonso 1996, 2007). With two
female leads in the film, it would have been possible to present a variety of
approaches to work-life balance. A feminist storyline would have worked to
dismantle the myth that women engineers must choose between job and
relationships, between career and family. In squandering an important opportunity
to be part of the solution, this film becomes part of the problem.
Julie’s attractiveness is established early in the film when Laura’s boss Jeff
comments on her appearance. Julie’s teammates ogle her (as does the audience)
when she reaches under a car (at a gratuitous camera angle), revealing her ‘‘tramp
stamp’’ lower-back tattoo. Later Julie’s boss Barry blatantly hits on her when his
wife is out of town. A single question in the study guide addresses this problematic
narrative: ‘‘Does the fact that Laura and Julie are attractive enter into any part of the
interaction? Should it?’’ With the film itself leaving Laura’s attractiveness in
question, and with no counter-story connecting sexual harassment with power and
control, educators can do little to overcome social mythology and the film’s
narrative at once.
The film and study guide do not present common harms caused by sexual
harassment, such as time and focus lost or mental health impacts (Tong 1983). The
only evidence of harm we see beyond Julie’s facial expressions is her feeding her
emotions: eating cake while exercising on a treadmill. Laura enters a room with an
unimaginably large piece of cake and declares this is ‘‘what the doctor ordered’’ as
they proceed to talk about their bad days at work. That this scene portrays a
gendered approach to dealing with stress (it would be unusual to have a scene in
which men exhibited these behaviors) is only part of the problem. The combination
of eating cake while exercising on a treadmill seems both physically dangerous and
potentially symptomatic of an eating disorder. While sexual harassment can
contribute to the development of eating disorders (Sexual Harassment Support
2010), the film does not present the cake-eating in this light, leaving most viewers
unaware of sexual harassment’s toll.
While Loui et al. (2010) describe the film as presenting ‘‘subtle sexual
harassment,’’ many actions are quite brazen (though some might not meet the legal
definition of sexual harassment). For example, after Julie tells her sister about being
ogled, Laura confronts Marty as his supervisor. His retort: ‘‘Why would she have a
tattoo if she didn’t want anyone to look at it?’’ When Barry the boss asks Julie to
‘‘grab some dinner’’ she replies ‘‘isn’t your wife out of town?’’ and Barry says
3 While the study guide says Laura is 29, the voiceover in the film establishes that she is 11 years older
than her sister who just graduated from college, identified in the study guide as 21.
Hidden in Plain View 201
123
smarmily ‘‘Yeah, that’s why I offered.’’ A more nuanced scenario might be for
Marty to deny looking at Julie at all, or for Barry to take cover in plausible
deniability, and claim he was asking to grab dinner as professionals (or as friends).
How to handle these situations (blatant or subtle) raises a series of interesting ethical
questions, but these are not presented in the study guide.
In addition to ogling Julie, Marty makes two racist comments to an African
American colleague, each likening him to an ape. Here again the portrayal is far
from subtle, and adding in Marty’s engineering incompetence, there is little to make
his character relatable. In actuality, acts of harassment are often committed by
people who are otherwise well respected, successful, and thought of as ‘‘good
people,’’ making a decision to confront inappropriate behavior more difficult.
The study guide asks: ‘‘Was Marty’s treatment of Warren harassment?’’ and
‘‘Should Laura have said something about Marty’s treatment of Warren (like she did
about the ogling of Julie)?’’ This second question is curious because Barry, the
project manager, was present at both incidents. Does team leadership not extend to
addressing interpersonal interactions, especially when they rise to this level of
hostility? Laura did not witness the interactions between Marty and Warren, nor
were they reported to her. While supervisors are legally and ethically responsible to
respond to bias incidents in the workplace, it seems that the standard being applied
to Laura lies beyond human capabilities. Instead of setting up a comparison between
gender and race-based harassment, it would have been interesting if Warren’s
character (or a different character altogether) were a woman of color, opening up a
discussion of intersectionality and the ways in which race and gender factor into a
single experience of harassment.
Three of eight study guide questions on gender focus on the ethics of perpetrator
behavior: ‘‘Are sexist comments disguised as ‘jokes’ acceptable? … Is it
permissible for a male employee to put his hand on a female employee’s shoulders?
Or vice versa? For a male employee to put his hand on another male employee’s
shoulders? Is it permissible for a male employee to compliment a female
employee’s appearance? Or vice versa?’’ This over-emphasis on perpetrators may
be directed toward preventing inappropriate conduct, but it leaves out not only those
who are sexually harassed, but also women and men acting as allies when friends
and colleagues experience harassment. In targeting compliance with certain
behavioral norms and in presenting situations that lack nuance and leave one right
answer, the film opts for unimaginative problem solving over transformative antisexist
education.
Questions that focus on the ethics of ally and respondent actions in the face of
harassment could refocus a problematic film in a more positive direction. For
example, Laura intervenes on Julie’s behalf expressly against her wishes in order to
stop Marty’s ogling. Understanding that sexual harassment is about power, this
intervention could seriously undermine Julie’s autonomy and moral agency. Asking
from the standpoint of an agent what else either Laura or Julie could have done,
scoping out the space of possible ethical action is an appropriate practice of feminist
ethics. Doing so could also lead to a discussion of institutional policies and the
responsibility of organizations in preventing harassment. This discussion would
indeed be complex and hearken back to Tronto’s (2001) ethical critique of
202 D. Riley
123
managerialism, as many institutions view supervisors as having specific legal
obligations that would preclude many of the options identified above: intervening
directly, as well as respecting Julie’s autonomy (or even maintaining her
confidentiality were that an issue) might put the institution at legal risk.
Moving Forward: Feminist Engineering Ethics
In order to develop feminist engineering ethics, scholars doing feminist work must
be able to use the word openly without negative repercussions. Though there
continue to be real costs to doing so, use of the f-word is becoming more common
(Riley et al. 2009), and claiming and naming feminist ethical approaches may be the
only way we can broach certain topics with integrity and accountability.
In lieu of a conclusion, as this conversation is just beginning, I offer four areas in
which we (feminists doing engineering ethics, engineers doing feminist ethics)
might move forward in developing feminist engineering ethics. This intersection
provides a wealth of opportunities for the work of feminist ethics to benefit
engineering ethics and vice versa.
First, we need to address questions of epistemology in engineering ethics, as well
as in engineering. When engineers dismiss educational outcomes related to
understanding social context, communicating effectively, and engaging ethical
problems, this devaluation is often rooted in a mistrust of or disrespect for ways of
knowing endemic to other disciplines. By teaching engineering ethics, students can
gain from philosophy’s ability to name these ways of knowing and probe their
consequences for thought and action. Feminist epistemologies can break the hold of
positivism in engineering and open new possibilities for the profession. Until we
wrestle with epistemology in the ways other disciplines have, we will be unable to
meet larger goals for the profession including producing engineers who are able to
fully engage with the social and ethical aspects of their work.
Second, questions about power, agency, and the structure of the profession are
sorely missing from most approaches to engineering ethics. We might adapt
Walker’s (1989) analysis to suggest that feminist engineering ethics might begin by
asking questions such as who counts morally in engineering? Who is served, who
benefits, and who pays the cost? What communities do engineers claim to represent,
and who is actually represented? What modes of communication facilitate
interactions in engineering, and who has access to these? How does professionalization
‘‘deform the abilities of all concerned to hear and be heard’’ (23)? Who
decides what is ethical? Who holds whom accountable and how?
Nelson’s (2001) work on identity and moral agency leads us to ask, how is
engineers’ moral agency constricted, both internally and externally? Do the ways in
which we form our identities as engineers serve to limit our range of moral thought
and action? Do others’ perceptions of us—management, the public—further
constrain our moral agency?
We cannot shy away from ethical questions that are deemed political. We must
wrestle, for example, with engineering’s embeddedness in militarism and war, with
its complicity with and facilitation of free market extremism wreaking havoc on a
Hidden in Plain View 203
123
global scale, and with its destruction of communities, non-human species, and
ecosystems in the name of ‘‘progress’’ or ‘‘development.’’
Third, feminist engineering ethics should interrogate forms of expression through
analysis of discourse and the construction of cases in engineering. Walker (1989)
notes the absence of the 2nd person plural in case studies, which excludes
collaborative deliberation and communication. She calls us to move away from
‘‘regimentation of moral reasoning into deductive argument; schematic examples in
which what is morally relevant is already selected and social-political context is
effaced; omission of continuing narratives that explore interpersonal sequels to
moral solutions’’ (24). In engineering, we have our work cut out for us, from
avoiding the use of passive voice that disguises agency, to getting beyond
reductionist single-answer approaches to technical and ethical problem solving. The
time is ripe to ask how are we constructing cases? What are our underlying
assumptions? Are people and interpersonal relations visible? Can we demonstrate to
students the ways in which communication is an ethical issue?
Fourth, what can be learned from other areas of scholarship—particularly
feminist professional ethics in other fields and feminist and postcolonial science and
technology studies—that might directly inform feminist engineering ethics?
Reviewing these literatures with an engineering ethical lens will provide new
avenues for research and strategies for change within the profession. It is in this area
of applied ethics that engineering ethicists may be able to offer a great deal to the
field of feminist ethics. The detailed and nuanced understanding of the intricacies of
ethics related to the development of technology can provide new questions explored
at the intersection of these fields, in areas such as environment and sustainability;
biotechnology; militarism and war; and globalization and development.
May the conversation continue.
Acknowledgments The author thanks participants in the DePauw Mellon workshop on Feminist Ethics,
particularly Meryl Altman and Jana Sawicki for their helpful comments on drafts of this work.
References
Allgood, G. (2010). Everyone deserves clean water. Association for practical and professional ethics mini
conference on engineering and social justice. March 6, 2010. http://www.onlineethics.org/
23422.aspx. Accessed May 26, 2011.
Andrew, B. (2001). Angels, rubbish collectors, and pursuers of erotic joy: The image of the ethical
woman. In P. DesAutels & J. Waugh (Eds.), Feminists doing ethics. Lanham, MD: Rowman &
Littlefield.
Baillie, C. (Ed.). (2006–2011). Synthesis lectures on engineers, technology and society. San Rafael, CA:
Morgan and Claypool.
Bartky, S. L. (1995). Feeding egos and tending wounds: Deference and disaffection in women’s
emotional labor. In M. Rogers (Ed.), Power, dignity and social structure: Readings in multicultural
social theory. New York: McGraw Hill.
Burton, B. K., & Dunn, C. P. (1996). Feminist ethics as moral grounding for stakeholder theory. Business
Ethics Quarterly, 6(2), 133–147.
Canon, K. G. (1988). Black womanist ethics. Eugene, OR: Wipf and Stock.
Card, C. (1995). Gender and moral luck [1990]. In V. Held (Ed.), Justice and care: Essential readings in
feminism. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.
Cockburn, C., & Dubravk, Z. (2002). The postwar moment: Militaries, masculinities and international
peacekeeping. London: Lawrence and Wishart.
204 D. Riley
123
Cowan, R. S. (1992). Genetic technology and reproductive choice: An ethics for autonomy. In D.
J. Kevles & L. Hood (Eds.), The code of codes: Scientific and social issues in the human genome
project. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Crenshaw, K. (1991). Mapping the margins: Intersectionality, identity politics, and violence against
women of color. Stanford Law Review, 43(6), 1241–1299.
Derry, R. (2002). Feminist theory and business ethics. In R. Frederick (Ed.), A companion to business
ethics. Oxford: Blackwell.
Engineering Social Justice and Peace. (2010). Website. http://www.esjp.org. Accessed 15 October 2010.
Fleddermann, C. B. (1999). Engineering ethics. Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice Hall.
Gilligan, C. (1982). In a different voice: Psychological theory and women’s development. Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press.
Harding, S., & Narayan, U. (1998). Border crossings: Multicultural and postcolonial feminist challenges
to philosophy (part II). Hypatia, 13(3), 1–5. See entire special issue.
Harris, C. E., Pritchard, M. S., & Rabins, M. J. (2005). Engineering ethics: Concepts and cases (3rd ed.).
Stamford, CT: Thomson Wadsworth.
Held, V. (Ed.). (1995). Justice and care: Essential readings in feminist ethics. Boulder, CO: Westview
Press.
Henry’s Daughters

. (2010). Paul Martin (director, writer, editor). PI: Jimmy Smith.
Co-PIs: Joe Herkert, Michael Loui, William Marcy, and Steven Nichols. Lubbock, TX: National
Institute for Engineering Ethics. More information, including study guide, available at http://
www.niee.org/2009%20website/niee/niee%20htm/ProductsServices-HenrysDaughters.htm. Accessed
15 October 2010.
Holmes, H. B., & Purdy, L. M. (Eds.). (1992). Feminist perspectives in medical ethics. Bloomington, IN:
Indiana University Press.
hooks, b. (1984). Feminist theory from margin to center. Boston, MA: South End Press.
Hugman, R., & Smith, D. (Eds.). (1995). Ethical issues in social work. New York: Routledge.
Jaggar, A. (2009a). The philosophical challenges of global gender justice. Philosophical Topics, 37(2), 1–15.
Jaggar, A. (2009b). Transnational cycles of gendered vulnerability: A prologue to a theory of global
gender justice. Philosophical Topics, 37(2), 33–52.
Johnson, D., & Wetmore, J. (2008). STS and ethics: Implications for engineering ethics. In E. Hackett, O.
Amsterdamska, M. Lynch, & J. Wajcman (Eds.), New handbook of science and technology studies.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Kardon, J. (2005). Concept of ‘‘Care’’ in engineering. Journal of Performance of Constructed Facilities,
19(3), 256–260.
Karnani, A. G. (2007). The mirage of marketing to the bottom of the pyramid. California Management
Review, 49(4), 90–111.
Kittay, E. (2009) The moral harm of migrant carework: Realizing a global right to care. Philosophical
Topics, 37(2), 53–74.
Koehn, D. (1998). Rethinking feminist ethics: Care, trust, and empathy. New York: Routledge.
Larson, A. L., & Freeman, R. E. (1997). Women’s studies and business ethics. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Loui, M. C., Smith, J. H., Herkert, J. R., & Nichols, S. P. (2010). Special session—Henry’s daughters: A
new engineering ethics movie. In Proceedings of the 40th ASEE/IEEE frontiers in education
conference, October 27–30, 2010, Washington, DC. http://fie-conference.org/fie2010/papers/
1134.pdf. Accessed August 17, 2011.
MacKinnon, K. (1979). Sexual harassment of working women. New Haven: Yale University Press.
Martin, M. W., & Schinzinger, R. (1996). Ethics in engineering (3rd ed.). New York: McGraw-Hill.
Mashburn, A. R., & Martin, J. T. (1999). The three faces of eve: Difference, dominance and beyond. In B.
W. Taylor, S. Rush, & R. J. Munro (Eds.), Feminist jurisprudence, women and the law: Critical
essays, research agenda, and bibliography. Littleton, CO: Rothman.
McGregor, S. (2006). Pumping out the profits. Embassy, March 29, 2006. http://www.embassymag.ca/
page/view/.2006.march.29.africapump. Accessed May 26, 2011.
Narayan, U. (1995). Colonialism and its others: Considerations on rights and care discourses. Hypatia,
10(2), 133–140.
Narayan, U., & Harding, S. (1998). Border crossings: Multicultural and postcolonial feminist challenges
to philosophy (part I). Hypatia, 13(2), 1–6. See entire special issue.
Nelson, H. L. (2001). Identity and free agency. In P. DesAutels & J. Waugh (Eds.), Feminists doing
ethics. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
Hidden in Plain View 205
123
Noddings, N. (1984). Caring: A feminine approach to ethics and moral education. Berkeley, CA:
University of California Press.
Okin, S. (1989). Justice, gender, and the family. New York: Basic Books.
Pantazidou, M., & Nair, I. (1999). Ethic of care: Guiding principles for engineering teaching and practice.
Journal of Engineering Education, 88, 205–212.
Parks, J. A. (1999). Ethical androcentrism and maternal substance addiction. International Journal of
Applied Philosophy, 13(2), 165–175.
Riley, D. M. (2008). Ethics in context, ethics in action: Getting beyond the individual professional in
engineering ethics education. ASEE Annual Conference Proceedings, June 22–25, Pittsburgh: PA.
Riley, D.M., Ellis, G., & Howe, H. (2004). ‘‘To move people from apathy’’: A multi-perspective approach
to ethics across the engineering curriculum. ASEE Annual Conference Proceedings, June 21–24,
Salt Lake City: UT.
Riley, D. M., Claris, L., & Ngambeki, I. (2006). The ethics blog: Students making connections among
ethics, thermodynamics, and life. ASEE Annual Conference Proceedings, June 18–21, Chicago: IL.
Riley, D., Pawley, A. L., Tucker, J., & Catalano, G. D. (2009). Feminisms in engineering education:
Transformative possibilities. National Women’s Studies Association Journal, 21(2), 21–40.
Seymour, E. (1995). The loss of women from science, mathematics, and engineering undergraduate
majors: An explanatory account. Science Education, 79(4), 437–473.
Sexual Harassment Support. (2010). Effects of sexual harassment. http://www.sexualharassmentsupport.
org/effects.html. Accessed 15 October 2010.
Subramaniam, B. (2001). The aliens have landed! Reflections on the rhetoric of biological invasions.
Meridians: Feminism, Race, Transnationalism, 2, 26–40.
Taylor, B. W., Rush, S., & Munro, R. J. (1999). Feminist Jurisprudence, women, and the law: Critical
essays, research agenda, and bibliography. Buffalo: Fred B. Rothman & Co.
Tong, R. (1983). Women, sex, and the law. Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Littlefield.
Tonso, K. L. (1996). The impact of cultural norms of women. Journal of Engineering Education, 85,
217–225.
Tonso, K. L. (2007). On the outskirts of engineering: Learning identity, gender, and power via
engineering practice. Rotterdam: Sense Publishers.
Tronto, J. C. (1987). Beyond gender difference to a theory of care. Signs, 12(4), 644–663.
Tronto, J. (1993). Moral boundaries: A political argument for an ethic of care. New York: Routledge.
Tronto, J. (2001). Does managing professionals affect professional ethics? Competence, autonomy, and
care. In P. DesAutels & J. Waugh (Eds.), Feminists doing ethics. Lanham, MD: Rowman &
Littlefield.
Vesilind, A. (2010). Engineering peace and justice: The responsibility of engineers to society. New York:
Springer.
Vesilind, A., & Gunn, A. (1998). Engineering, ethics, and the environment. New York: Cambridge
University Press.
Vidhu, V. (2004). Engendering development: Limits of feminist theories of justice. Economic and
Political Weekly, 29(49), 5246–5252.
Wacjman, J. (1991). Feminism confronts technology. University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University
Press.
Walker, M. U. (1989). Moral understandings: Alternative ‘‘Epistemology’’ for a feminist ethics. Hypatia,
4(2), 15–28.
Warren, K. (2000). Ecofeminist philosophy: A western perspective on what it is and why it matters.
Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
Weston, G., & Aubry, J. (1990). Montreal’s mass killer marc Le´pine’s hatred fed on failure, The Toronto
Star, February 8, 1990, p. A18.
Whitbeck, C. (1983). Afterword to The maternal instinct (1982). In J. Treblicot (Ed.), Mothering: Essays
in feminist theory. Totowa, NJ: Rowman & Allanheld.
Whitbeck, C. (1995). Teaching ethics to scientists and engineers: Moral agents and moral problems.
Science and Engineering Ethics, 1(3), 299–308.
Whitbeck, C. (1998). Ethics in engineering practice and research. New York: Cambridge University
Press.
Wicks, A. C., Gilbert, D. R., & Freeman, R. E. (1994). A feminist reinterpretation of the stakeholder
concept. Business Ethics Quarterly, 4, 475–497.
Young, I. M. (1990). Justice and the politics of difference. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
206 D. Riley
123
Copyright of Science & Engineering Ethics is the property of Springer Science & Business Media B.V. and its
content may not be copied or emailed to multiple sites or posted to a listserv without the copyright holder’s
express written permission. However, users may print, download, or email articles for individual use.

Order from us and get better grades. We are the service you have been looking for.